Aristophanes: A Guide to Selected Sources: Difference between revisions

m (Text replace - "howtoquoteguide" to "howtoquote")
No edit summary
Line 7: Line 7:
== Comedy and Ancient Biography ==
== Comedy and Ancient Biography ==


{{#lemma: Aristophanes’ ''Vita'' | [[Passage 1]]}} raises pertinent issues for ancient poetic biographies, since much of their material derives from comedy (Lefkowitz 2012). That of Aristophanes is no exception, being ‘largely a mere stringing together of passages from his plays which the ancient scholiasts considered to be reliably autobiographical.’ (Cartledge 1999: xiii). For the most part, historical facts about Aristophanes’ life must be sought elsewhere (see Cartledge 1999: xiii-xviii), but the ''Vita''’s and scholiasts’ assumption is worth probing for what it can teach us about ancient biography. Three characteristics of Old Comedy seem particularly relevant:  
{{#lemma: Aristophanes’ ''Vita'' | [[Passage 1]]}} raises pertinent issues for ancient poetic biographies, since much of its material derives from comedy (Lefkowitz 2012). That of Aristophanes is no exception, being ‘largely a mere stringing together of passages from his plays which the ancient scholiasts considered to be reliably autobiographical.’ (Cartledge 1999: xiii). For the most part, historical facts about Aristophanes’ life must be sought elsewhere (see Cartledge 1999: xiii-xviii), but the ''Vita''’s and scholiasts’ assumption is worth probing for what it can teach us about ancient biography. Three characteristics of Old Comedy seem particularly relevant:  


(1) The genre’s ambiguous position on the boundary between fiction and reality. Like some iambic (invective) poetry, comedy refers to people and events in the ‘real’ world (see [[Archilochus: A Guide to Selected Sources|Guide to Archilochus]]; Rosen 1988, 2007). Ancient commentators and biographers tend to treat its satirical statements as factual (Halliwell 1984).
(1) The genre’s ambiguous position on the boundary between fiction and reality. Like some iambic (invective) poetry, comedy refers to people and events in the ‘real’ world (see [[Archilochus: A Guide to Selected Sources|Guide to Archilochus]]; Rosen 1988, 2007). Ancient commentators and biographers tend to treat its satirical statements as factual (Halliwell 1984).
Line 15: Line 15:
The literariness of ‘stage autobiographies’ and their inseparability from the dynamics of comic competition is well illustrated by the confrontation between Aristophanes and Cratinus (see Sidwell 1995; Luppe 2000; Rosen 2000; Biles 2002, 2011; Bakola 2008, 2010). In {{#lemma: Knights | [[Passage 4]]}} (424 BCE), Aristophanes represented his rival as an alcoholic has-been, probably literalizing a wine metaphor in which Cratinus had laid claim to the ‘Dionysian’ heritage of Archilochean iambos (Biles 2002, 2011). The following year, Cratinus responded to Aristophanes’ insult by creating an entire drama (''Pytine'') with himself as (anti-?)hero—the legitimate, alcoholic husband of a despairing Comedy. The play was a resounding success, trouncing Aristophanes’ ''Clouds'', which came third. In the ''Clouds''’ (re-written) {{#lemma: ''parabasis'' | [[Passage 5]]}}, the poet describes the defeat as one of his greatest disappointments.
The literariness of ‘stage autobiographies’ and their inseparability from the dynamics of comic competition is well illustrated by the confrontation between Aristophanes and Cratinus (see Sidwell 1995; Luppe 2000; Rosen 2000; Biles 2002, 2011; Bakola 2008, 2010). In {{#lemma: Knights | [[Passage 4]]}} (424 BCE), Aristophanes represented his rival as an alcoholic has-been, probably literalizing a wine metaphor in which Cratinus had laid claim to the ‘Dionysian’ heritage of Archilochean iambos (Biles 2002, 2011). The following year, Cratinus responded to Aristophanes’ insult by creating an entire drama (''Pytine'') with himself as (anti-?)hero—the legitimate, alcoholic husband of a despairing Comedy. The play was a resounding success, trouncing Aristophanes’ ''Clouds'', which came third. In the ''Clouds''’ (re-written) {{#lemma: ''parabasis'' | [[Passage 5]]}}, the poet describes the defeat as one of his greatest disappointments.


(3) As this example demonstrates (see also Guides to [[Euripides: A Guide to Selected Sources|Euripides]] and [[Aeschylus: A Guide to Selected Sources|Aeschylus]]), ancient comedians took great delight in making poets resemble their works. The biographers’ tendency to extrapolate poets’ lives from their literary outputs is a closely related phenomenon (Graziosi 2006: 164-5). Both reflect the ancient view, humorously embodied and stated by Agathon in Aristophanes’ ''Thesmophoriazusae'' (149-52), that composing poetry requires imitative identification with one’s creations. From here to the cliché that life imitates art and vice-versa is a small step. Biographers played the game of generating lives from art with varying degrees of earnestness and sophistication. The fact that they considered it unproblematic reveals the differences between ancient and biography and our own (Momigliano 1993, Graziosi 2002, Hägg 2012). Historicity was not a priority, nor was historical evidence readily available; other agendas were in play (see Bing 1993, Graziosi 2002).
(3) As this example demonstrates (see also Guides to [[Euripides: A Guide to Selected Sources|Euripides]] and [[Aeschylus: A Guide to Selected Sources|Aeschylus]]), ancient comedians took great delight in making poets resemble their works. The biographers’ tendency to extrapolate poets’ lives from their literary outputs is a closely related phenomenon (Graziosi 2006: 164-5). Both reflect the ancient view, humorously embodied and stated by Agathon in Aristophanes’ ''Thesmophoriazusae'' (149-52), that composing poetry requires imitative identification with one’s creations. From here to the cliché that life imitates art and vice-versa is a small step. Biographers played the game of generating lives from art with varying degrees of earnestness and sophistication. The fact that they considered it unproblematic reveals the differences between ancient and biography and our own (Momigliano 1993; Graziosi 2002; Hägg 2012). Historicity was not a priority, nor was historical evidence readily available; other agendas were in play (see Bing 1993; Graziosi 2002).


== The ''Vita'' on Aristophanes as a hero of democracy ==
== The ''Vita'' on Aristophanes as a hero of democracy ==
Line 25: Line 25:
== Aristophanes’ Socrates and Plato’s Aristophanes ==
== Aristophanes’ Socrates and Plato’s Aristophanes ==


The ''Vita''’s deafening silence on the subject of Socrates is in keeping with its pro-democratic and pro-Aristophanic positioning. In Plato’s ''Republic'', democracy is ranked the second-worst type of constitution (see Scott 2000). The {{#lemma: ''Apology'' | [[Passage 16]]}} makes a direct connection between reputational damage caused by Aristophanes’ portrayal of Socrates in ''Clouds'' and his subsequent condemnation to death by a popular jury. {{#lemma: Some | [[Passage 18]]}} embellished this view, {{#lemma: others | [[Passage 17]]}} argued that a faithful representation was not intended—to which Plato would presumably have responded by pointing to the dangers of misreading. Aristophanes’ caricature is a mélange of Pre-Socratic, sophist, and guru of newfangled mysteries, whose relationship to the historical Socrates, is, unsurprisingly, anything but straightforward (see Bowie 1993: 112-24, Rashed 2009: 107-36, Konstan 2011: 75-90, Laks/Saetta Cottone 2013). {{#lemma: Aelian | [[Passage 19]]}}, who intensifies the ''Apology''’s critical stance, says that when foreigners wondered whom the masked likeness represented, Socrates stood up in the audience and remained standing throughout the play—a paradoxical reminder of Plato’s view that poetry is at the third remove from truth.
The ''Vita''’s deafening silence on the subject of Socrates is in keeping with its pro-democratic and pro-Aristophanic positioning. In Plato’s ''Republic'', democracy is ranked the second-worst type of constitution (see Scott 2000). The {{#lemma: ''Apology'' | [[Passage 16]]}} makes a direct connection between reputational damage caused by Aristophanes’ portrayal of Socrates in ''Clouds'' and his subsequent condemnation to death by a popular jury. {{#lemma: Some | [[Passage 18]]}} embellished this view, {{#lemma: others | [[Passage 17]]}} argued that a faithful representation was not intended—to which Plato would presumably have responded by pointing to the dangers of misreading. Aristophanes’ caricature is a mélange of Pre-Socratic, sophist, and guru of newfangled mysteries, whose relationship to the historical Socrates, is, unsurprisingly, anything but straightforward (see Bowie 1993: 112-24; Rashed 2009: 107-36; Konstan 2011: 75-90; Laks/Saetta Cottone 2013). {{#lemma: Aelian | [[Passage 19]]}}, who intensifies the ''Apology''’s critical stance, says that when foreigners wondered whom the masked likeness represented, Socrates stood up in the audience and remained standing throughout the play—a paradoxical reminder of Plato’s view that poetry is at the third remove from truth.


{{#lemma: Olympiodorus | [[Passage 20]]}}, by contrast, makes Plato an admirer of Aristophanes. Certainly his portrait in the {{#lemma: ''Symposium'' | [[Passage 21]]}} could not be more gracious (see Hunter 2004: 60-71). A bout of hiccups prevents Aristophanes, ‘who thinks of nothing but Dionysos and Aphrodite’ (177e), from taking his allotted place in the sequence of ''encomia'' to love. His fable about human origins makes love a literal quest for one’s ‘other half’—our ancestors were bisected by the gods in punishment for ''hybris'' (189a-193d). Invective is notably absent; the speech displays only the comic poet’s charm and imaginative genius—and Plato’s mastery thereof. Diotima’s metaphysical revelations subsequently demonstrate its lack of understanding.
{{#lemma: Olympiodorus | [[Passage 20]]}}, by contrast, makes Plato an admirer of Aristophanes. Certainly his portrait in the {{#lemma: ''Symposium'' | [[Passage 21]]}} could not be more gracious (see Hunter 2004: 60-71). A bout of hiccups prevents Aristophanes, ‘who thinks of nothing but Dionysos and Aphrodite’ (177e), from taking his allotted place in the sequence of ''encomia'' to love. His fable about human origins makes love a literal quest for one’s ‘other half’—our ancestors were bisected by the gods in punishment for ''hybris'' (189a-193d). Invective is notably absent; the speech displays only the comic poet’s charm and imaginative genius—and Plato’s mastery thereof. Diotima’s metaphysical revelations subsequently demonstrate its lack of understanding.
Line 38: Line 38:


<div id="bibliography">
<div id="bibliography">
* Bakola, E. 2008. ‘The Drunk, the Reformer and the Teacher: Agonistic Poetics and the Construction of Persona in the Comic Poets of the Fifth Century.’ ''CCJ'' 54: 1-29.
*Bakola, E. 2008. ‘The Drunk, the Reformer and the Teacher: Agonistic Poetics and the Construction of Persona in the Comic Poets of the Fifth Century.’ ''CCJ'' 54: 1-29.
** 2010. ''Cratinus and the Art of Comedy''. Oxford.
 
* Biles, Z. 2002. ‘Intertextual Biography in the Rivalry of Cratinus and Aristophanes.’ ''AJP'' 123: 169-204.
**2010. ''Cratinus and the Art of Comedy''. Oxford.
** 2011. ''Aristophanes and the Poetics of Competition''. Cambridge.
 
* Bing, P. 1993. ‘The Bios-Tradition and Poets’ Lives in Hellenistic Poetry.’ In R. Rosen and J. Farrell eds. ''Nomodeiktes: Greek Studies in Honor of Martin Ostwald''. Ann Arbor. 619-31.  
Biles, Z. 2002. ‘Intertextual Biography in the Rivalry of Cratinus and Aristophanes.’ ''AJP'' 123: 169-204.
* Bowie, A. 1993. ''Aristophanes: Myth, Ritual, and Comedy''. Cambridge.
 
* Cartledge, P. A. 1999 (1990). ''Aristophanes and his Theatre of the Absurd.'' Bristol.
**2011. ''Aristophanes and the Poetics of Competition''. Cambridge.
* Dobrov, G.W. 1995. ‘The Poet’s Voice in the Evolution of Dramatic Dialogism.’ In Dobrov ed. ''Beyond Aristophanes: Transition and Diversity in Greek Comedy.'' Atlanta. 47-97.
 
** ed. 2010. ''Brill’s Companion to the Study of Greek Comedy.'' Leiden.
Bing, P. 1993. ‘The Bios-Tradition and Poets’ Lives in Hellenistic Poetry.’ In R. Rosen and J. Farrell eds. 1993, ''Nomodeiktes: Greek Studies in Honor of Martin Ostwald''. Ann Arbor. 619-31.  
* Goldhill, S. 1991. ''The Poet’s Voice: Essays on Poetics and Greek Literature.'' Cambridge.
 
* Graziosi, B. 2002. ''Inventing Homer: the Early Reception of Epic''. Cambridge.
Bowie, A. 1993. ''Aristophanes: Myth, Ritual, and Comedy''. Cambridge.
** 2006. ‘Il rapporto tra autore ed opera nella tradizione biografica greca.’ In F. Roscalla ed. ''L’autore e l’opera. Attribuzioni, appropriazioni, apocrifi nella Grecia antica''. Pisa. 155-75.
 
* Hägg, T. 2012. ''The Art of Biography in Antiquity''. Cambridge.
Burges Watson, S. “Orpheus’ Erotic Mysteries: Plato, Pederasty and the Zagreus Myth in Phanocles Fragment 1.” Forthcoming, ''BICS'' 2014.
* Halliwell, S. 1984. ‘Ancient Interpretations of ὀνομαστὶ κωμωιδεῖν in Aristophanes.’ ''CQ'' 34: 83-8.
 
** 1991. ‘Comic Satire and Freedom of Speech in Classical Athens.’ ''JHS'' 111: 48-70.
Cartledge, P. A. 1999 (1990). ''Aristophanes and his Theatre of the Absurd''. Bristol.
* Harvey D. and Wilkins J. eds. 2000. ''The Rivals of Aristophanes: Studies in Athenian Old Comedy''. London.
 
* Henderson, J. 1998-2007. ''Aristophanes''. Edited with Translation. Cambridge MA.
Dobrov, G.W. 1995. ‘The Poet’s Voice in the Evolution of Dramatic Dialogism.’ In G.W. Dobrov ed. 1995, ''Beyond Aristophanes: Transition and Diversity in Greek Comedy''. Atlanta. 47-97.
* Hunter, R. 2004. ''Plato’s Symposium''. Oxford.
 
** 2009. ''Critical Moments in Classical Literature: Studies in the Ancient View of Literature and its Uses''. Cambridge.
**ed. 2010. ''Brill’s Companion to the Study of Greek Comedy''. Leiden.
* Kassel, R. and Austin, C. 1984. ''Poetae Comici Graeci. Vol. 3.2: Aristophanes Testimonia et Fragmenta''. Berlin.
 
* Konstan, D. 2011. ‘Socrates in Aristophanes’ Clouds.’ In D. Morrison ed. ''The Cambridge Companion to Socrates''. Cambridge. 75-90.
Goldhill, S. 1991. ''The Poet’s Voice: Essays on Poetics and Greek Literature''. Cambridge.
* Laks, A. and Saetta Cottone, R. 2013. ''Comedie et Philosophie. Socrate et les Presocratiques dans les Nuées d’ Aristophane''. Paris.
 
* Lefkowitz, M. 2012 (1981). ''The Lives of the Greek Poets''. Baltimore.
Graziosi, B. 2002. ''Inventing Homer: the Early Reception of Epic''. Cambridge.
* Luppe, W. 2000. ‘The Rivalry between Aristophanes and Kratinos.’ In Harvey/Wilkins eds. 15-23.
 
* MacDowell, D. 1971. ''Aristophanes’ Wasps. Edited with Introduction and Commentary''. Oxford.
**2006. ‘Il rapporto tra autore ed opera nella tradizione biografica greca.’ In F. Roscalla ed. 2006, ''L’autore e l’opera. Attribuzioni, appropriazioni, apocrifi nella Grecia antica''. Pisa. 155-75.
* Momigliano, A. 1993 (1971). ''The Development of Greek Biography''. Cambridge MA.
 
* Olson, S. D. 2010. ‘Comedy, Politics, and Society.’ In Dobrov ed. 35-70.
Hägg, T. 2012. ''The Art of Biography in Antiquity''. Cambridge.
* Rashed, M. 2009. ‘Aristophanes and the Socrates of the ''Phaedo''.’ ''Oxford Studies in Ancient Philosophy'' 36: 107-36.
 
* Rosen, R. 1988. ''Old Comedy and the Iambographic Tradition''. Atlanta, GA.
Halliwell, S. 1984. ‘Ancient Interpretations of ὀνομαστὶ κωμωιδεῖν in Aristophanes.’ ''CQ'' 34: 83-8.
* Rosen, R. M. 2000. ‘Cratinus’ ''Pytine'' and the Construction of the Comic Self.’ In Harvey/Wilkins ed. 23-40.
 
** 2007. ''Making Mockery: the Poetics of Ancient Satire''. Oxford.
**1991. ‘Comic Satire and Freedom of Speech in Classical Athens.’ ''JHS'' 111: 48-70.
** 2010. ‘Aristophanes.’ In Dobrov ed. 227-78.
 
* Rusten, J. ed. 2011. ''The Birth of Comedy. Texts, Documents, and Art from Athenian Comic Competitions'', 486-280. Baltimore.
Harvey, D. and Wilkins, J. eds. 2000. ''The Rivals of Aristophanes: Studies in Athenian Old Comedy''. London.
* Scott, D. 2000. ‘Plato’s Critique of the Democratic Character.’ ''Phronesis'' 45: 19-37.
 
* Sidwell, K. 1995. ‘Poetic Rivalry and the Caricature of Comic Poets: Cratinus’ ''Pytine'' and Aristophanes’ ''Wasps''.’ In A Griffith ed. ''Stage Directions: Essays in Ancient Drama in Honour of E. W. Handley''. London. 56-80.
Henderson, J. 1998-2007. ''Aristophanes. Edited with Translation''. Cambridge MA.
* Sommerstein, A. H. 1990-2012. ''The Comedies of Aristophanes''. Edited with Translation and Notes. Warminster.
 
* Storey, I. 2003. ''Eupolis: Poet of Old Comedy.'' Oxford.
Hunter, R. 2004. ''Plato’s Symposium''. Oxford.
 
**2009. ''Critical Moments in Classical Literature: Studies in the Ancient View of Literature and its Uses''. Cambridge.
 
Kassel, R. and Austin, C. 1984. ''Poetae Comici Graeci. Vol. 3.2: Aristophanes Testimonia et Fragmenta''. Berlin.
 
Konstan, D. 2011. ‘Socrates in Aristophanes’ Clouds.’ In D. Morrison ed. 2011, ''The Cambridge Companion to Socrates''. Cambridge. 75-90.
 
Laks, A. and Saetta Cottone, R. 2013. ''Comedie et Philosophie. Socrate et les Presocratiques dans les Nuées d’Aristophane''. Paris.
 
Lefkowitz, M. 2012 (1981). ''The Lives of the Greek Poets''. Baltimore.
 
Luppe, W. 2000. ‘The Rivalry between Aristophanes and Kratinos.’ In D. Harvey and J. Wilkins eds. 2000: 15-23.
 
MacDowell, D. 1971. ''Aristophanes’ Wasps. Edited with Introduction and Commentary''. Oxford.
 
Momigliano, A. 1993 (1971). ''The Development of Greek Biography''. Cambridge MA.
 
Olson, S. D. 2010. ‘Comedy, Politics, and Society.’ In G.W. Dobrov ed. 2010: 35-70.  
 
Rashed, M. 2009. ‘Aristophanes and the Socrates of the Phaedo.’ ''OSAP'' 36: 107-36.
 
Rosen, R.M. 1988. ''Old Comedy and the Iambographic Tradition''. Atlanta, GA.
 
**2000. ‘Cratinus’ Pytine and the Construction of the Comic Self.’ In D. Harvey and J. Wilkins eds. 2000: 23-40.
 
**2007. ''Making Mockery: the Poetics of Ancient Satire''. Oxford.
 
**2010. ‘Aristophanes.’ In G.W. Dobrov ed. 2010: 227-78.
 
Rusten, J. ed. 2011. ''The Birth of Comedy. Texts, Documents, and Art from Athenian Comic Competitions, 486-280''. Baltimore.
 
Scott, D. 2000. ‘Plato’s Critique of the Democratic Character.’ ''Phronesis'' 45: 19-37.
 
Sidwell, K. 1995. ‘Poetic Rivalry and the Caricature of Comic Poets: Cratinus’ Pytine and Aristophanes’ Wasps.’ In A. Griffith ed. 1995, ''Stage Directions: Essays in Ancient Drama in Honour of E. W. Handley''. London. 56-80.  
 
Sommerstein, A. H. ed. 1990-2012. ''The Comedies of Aristophanes''. Warminster.
 
Storey, I. 2003. ''Eupolis: Poet of Old Comedy''. Oxford.
 
</div>
</div>
</div>
</div>
<div id="notes"></div>
<div id="notes"></div>

Revision as of 00:11, 1 September 2014

Correlate the sources mentioned in the guide to those listed in the margin using the mouse.

Sarah Burges Watson

How to quote this guide

Aristophanes, Athenian Vita (ch. 1) Passage 2 Passage 12 poet of Old Comedy, was born in the 450s and died ca. 386 BCE. His earliest plays, beginning with Banqueters (427), were produced by Callistratus or Philonides Vita (ch. 2) Passage 3, a decision which Aristophanes defends in Knights Passage 4 (512-19), probably responding to comic jibes Vita (ch. 2) Passage 3 that he was ‘toiling for others’. He won at least six times in the Athenian dramatic festivals. Eleven of his comedies survive. We have titles of thirty-two more and almost a thousand fragments. Sources on Aristophanes are collected by Kassel/Austin 1984 (Greek) and Rusten 2011 (English). His plays have been translated into English by Sommerstein and Henderson.

Comedy and Ancient Biography

Aristophanes’ Vita Passage 1 raises pertinent issues for ancient poetic biographies, since much of its material derives from comedy (Lefkowitz 2012). That of Aristophanes is no exception, being ‘largely a mere stringing together of passages from his plays which the ancient scholiasts considered to be reliably autobiographical.’ (Cartledge 1999: xiii). For the most part, historical facts about Aristophanes’ life must be sought elsewhere (see Cartledge 1999: xiii-xviii), but the Vita’s and scholiasts’ assumption is worth probing for what it can teach us about ancient biography. Three characteristics of Old Comedy seem particularly relevant:

(1) The genre’s ambiguous position on the boundary between fiction and reality. Like some iambic (invective) poetry, comedy refers to people and events in the ‘real’ world (see Guide to Archilochus; Rosen 1988, 2007). Ancient commentators and biographers tend to treat its satirical statements as factual (Halliwell 1984).

(2) The prominence of the poet’s voice, especially in the parabasis, a convention whereby the chorus turned to address the audience on behalf of, and sometimes in the voice of, the comic poet (see Hubbard 1991). That voice—fragmented, unstable, and elusive—is not the unmediated voice of a historical figure, but a ‘fictionalized representation of the author’ (Goldhill 1991), in dialogue with similarly fictionalized representations by/of his rivals and enemies (see Dobrov 1995; Storey 2003; Bakola 2008; Rosen 2010; Biles 2011).

The literariness of ‘stage autobiographies’ and their inseparability from the dynamics of comic competition is well illustrated by the confrontation between Aristophanes and Cratinus (see Sidwell 1995; Luppe 2000; Rosen 2000; Biles 2002, 2011; Bakola 2008, 2010). In Knights Passage 4 (424 BCE), Aristophanes represented his rival as an alcoholic has-been, probably literalizing a wine metaphor in which Cratinus had laid claim to the ‘Dionysian’ heritage of Archilochean iambos (Biles 2002, 2011). The following year, Cratinus responded to Aristophanes’ insult by creating an entire drama (Pytine) with himself as (anti-?)hero—the legitimate, alcoholic husband of a despairing Comedy. The play was a resounding success, trouncing Aristophanes’ Clouds, which came third. In the Clouds’ (re-written) parabasis Passage 5, the poet describes the defeat as one of his greatest disappointments.

(3) As this example demonstrates (see also Guides to Euripides and Aeschylus), ancient comedians took great delight in making poets resemble their works. The biographers’ tendency to extrapolate poets’ lives from their literary outputs is a closely related phenomenon (Graziosi 2006: 164-5). Both reflect the ancient view, humorously embodied and stated by Agathon in Aristophanes’ Thesmophoriazusae (149-52), that composing poetry requires imitative identification with one’s creations. From here to the cliché that life imitates art and vice-versa is a small step. Biographers played the game of generating lives from art with varying degrees of earnestness and sophistication. The fact that they considered it unproblematic reveals the differences between ancient and biography and our own (Momigliano 1993; Graziosi 2002; Hägg 2012). Historicity was not a priority, nor was historical evidence readily available; other agendas were in play (see Bing 1993; Graziosi 2002).

The Vita on Aristophanes as a hero of democracy

These considerations go some way towards explaining the Vita Unknown’s literalistic reading of Aristophanes’ persona. The most prominent ‘event’ in Aristophanes’ autobiography is his feud with the demagogue Cleon Passage 9 Passage 10 Passage 11, the target of Knights. The hostility supposedly arose when Cleon brought an accusation that Aristophanes was foreign (he had Aeginetan connections Vita (ch. 3) Ach. 652-4 (=Passage 6) Passage 2 Passage 3 Passage 12 Passage 13 Passage 14) and that, in Babylonians (426 BCE), he had slandered Athenian officials in the presence of foreigners. Most modern scholars accept that Cleon brought an action; Acharnians 381-23 Passage 10a suggests that it was rejected. In connection with the comic poet’s defeat of the ‘tyrannical’ Cleon, the Vita also repeats Aristophanes’ hyperbolic claim that he quashed the ‘informers’ (Wasps 1029-504 Passage 7 // Vita 4 Unknown), who were making prosecutions for the sake of personal profit (see MacDowell 1971: 1-4). These achievements are the cornerstones of the Vita’s portrayal of Aristophanes as a crusader for democracy.

The vehemently pro-democratic stance of the Vita Unknown (5), which probably took shape in the context of Hellenistic monarchy (Bing 1993), is surprising. In the Vita, to eulogize Aristophanes is to be pro-democracy. Ps. Xenophon (Ath. Pol. 2.18) makes a close connection between Old Comedy and democracy: invective is the people’s weapon against its enemies. Platonius Passage 15b follows suit. (See Hunter 2009: 104-6; Olson 2010: 37-45). According to Aristophanes’ rhetoric, frank and free speech—the hallmark of Athenian democracy—is the comic poet’s duty, even when this means putting one’s head on the block, like Dicaeopolis in the Acharnians Passage 6. It is worth considering how such passages may have resonated when transposed to a Hellenistic context. The Vita twice confronts Aristophanes with monarchy. Dicaeopolis claims that the king of Persia asked whether Athens or Sparta had received more abuse from Aristophanes, since such wise instruction was sure to tip the scales favourably in the Peloponnesian War. Scholars have noted with horror that the Vita Unknown (6) reports this joke as biographical ‘fact’. To repeat the story, however, is also (as Borges’ Pierre Menard might suggest) to re-stage the confrontation between Greek democracy and Eastern tyranny in a way that leaves the dignity of both sides intact and underlines the social benefits of comedy’s teaching. The same may be said of the anecdote (Vita 6) that Plato sent Aristophanes’ plays to Dionysius, the Sicilian tyrant whom, in the Seventh Letter, he cultivates as a potential philosopher-king. The Vita says that the plays were intended to provide instruction about the Athenian constitution—i.e. democracy.

Aristophanes’ Socrates and Plato’s Aristophanes

The Vita’s deafening silence on the subject of Socrates is in keeping with its pro-democratic and pro-Aristophanic positioning. In Plato’s Republic, democracy is ranked the second-worst type of constitution (see Scott 2000). The Apology Passage 16 makes a direct connection between reputational damage caused by Aristophanes’ portrayal of Socrates in Clouds and his subsequent condemnation to death by a popular jury. Some Passage 18 embellished this view, others Passage 17 argued that a faithful representation was not intended—to which Plato would presumably have responded by pointing to the dangers of misreading. Aristophanes’ caricature is a mélange of Pre-Socratic, sophist, and guru of newfangled mysteries, whose relationship to the historical Socrates, is, unsurprisingly, anything but straightforward (see Bowie 1993: 112-24; Rashed 2009: 107-36; Konstan 2011: 75-90; Laks/Saetta Cottone 2013). Aelian Passage 19, who intensifies the Apology’s critical stance, says that when foreigners wondered whom the masked likeness represented, Socrates stood up in the audience and remained standing throughout the play—a paradoxical reminder of Plato’s view that poetry is at the third remove from truth.

Olympiodorus Passage 20, by contrast, makes Plato an admirer of Aristophanes. Certainly his portrait in the Symposium Passage 21 could not be more gracious (see Hunter 2004: 60-71). A bout of hiccups prevents Aristophanes, ‘who thinks of nothing but Dionysos and Aphrodite’ (177e), from taking his allotted place in the sequence of encomia to love. His fable about human origins makes love a literal quest for one’s ‘other half’—our ancestors were bisected by the gods in punishment for hybris (189a-193d). Invective is notably absent; the speech displays only the comic poet’s charm and imaginative genius—and Plato’s mastery thereof. Diotima’s metaphysical revelations subsequently demonstrate its lack of understanding.

Old Comedy versus New

Plato’s critique of Aristophanes is echoed in Plutarch’s elitist and immensely hostile Comparison of Aristophanes and Menander Passage 22, which, like much Hellenistic writing, is also influenced by Aristotle’s Passage 23 censorship of Old Comedy’s malicious humour (see Hunter 2009: 78-89). The developmental narrative in Vita 13 Vita, ch. 1 carefully exempts Aristophanes from this charge: he softened his predecessors’ invective with charm, giving the genre its solemnity and utility. Invective, however, remains an essential—and positive—generic characteristic. When curbed by legal restrictions (for which evidence is lacking—see Halliwell 1991), Old Comedy becomes New; Aristophanes’ Cocalus paves the way.


Bibliography

  • Bakola, E. 2008. ‘The Drunk, the Reformer and the Teacher: Agonistic Poetics and the Construction of Persona in the Comic Poets of the Fifth Century.’ CCJ 54: 1-29.
    • 2010. Cratinus and the Art of Comedy. Oxford.

Biles, Z. 2002. ‘Intertextual Biography in the Rivalry of Cratinus and Aristophanes.’ AJP 123: 169-204.

    • 2011. Aristophanes and the Poetics of Competition. Cambridge.

Bing, P. 1993. ‘The Bios-Tradition and Poets’ Lives in Hellenistic Poetry.’ In R. Rosen and J. Farrell eds. 1993, Nomodeiktes: Greek Studies in Honor of Martin Ostwald. Ann Arbor. 619-31.

Bowie, A. 1993. Aristophanes: Myth, Ritual, and Comedy. Cambridge.

Burges Watson, S. “Orpheus’ Erotic Mysteries: Plato, Pederasty and the Zagreus Myth in Phanocles Fragment 1.” Forthcoming, BICS 2014.

Cartledge, P. A. 1999 (1990). Aristophanes and his Theatre of the Absurd. Bristol.

Dobrov, G.W. 1995. ‘The Poet’s Voice in the Evolution of Dramatic Dialogism.’ In G.W. Dobrov ed. 1995, Beyond Aristophanes: Transition and Diversity in Greek Comedy. Atlanta. 47-97.

    • ed. 2010. Brill’s Companion to the Study of Greek Comedy. Leiden.

Goldhill, S. 1991. The Poet’s Voice: Essays on Poetics and Greek Literature. Cambridge.

Graziosi, B. 2002. Inventing Homer: the Early Reception of Epic. Cambridge.

    • 2006. ‘Il rapporto tra autore ed opera nella tradizione biografica greca.’ In F. Roscalla ed. 2006, L’autore e l’opera. Attribuzioni, appropriazioni, apocrifi nella Grecia antica. Pisa. 155-75.

Hägg, T. 2012. The Art of Biography in Antiquity. Cambridge.

Halliwell, S. 1984. ‘Ancient Interpretations of ὀνομαστὶ κωμωιδεῖν in Aristophanes.’ CQ 34: 83-8.

    • 1991. ‘Comic Satire and Freedom of Speech in Classical Athens.’ JHS 111: 48-70.

Harvey, D. and Wilkins, J. eds. 2000. The Rivals of Aristophanes: Studies in Athenian Old Comedy. London.

Henderson, J. 1998-2007. Aristophanes. Edited with Translation. Cambridge MA.

Hunter, R. 2004. Plato’s Symposium. Oxford.

    • 2009. Critical Moments in Classical Literature: Studies in the Ancient View of Literature and its Uses. Cambridge.

Kassel, R. and Austin, C. 1984. Poetae Comici Graeci. Vol. 3.2: Aristophanes Testimonia et Fragmenta. Berlin.

Konstan, D. 2011. ‘Socrates in Aristophanes’ Clouds.’ In D. Morrison ed. 2011, The Cambridge Companion to Socrates. Cambridge. 75-90.

Laks, A. and Saetta Cottone, R. 2013. Comedie et Philosophie. Socrate et les Presocratiques dans les Nuées d’Aristophane. Paris.

Lefkowitz, M. 2012 (1981). The Lives of the Greek Poets. Baltimore.

Luppe, W. 2000. ‘The Rivalry between Aristophanes and Kratinos.’ In D. Harvey and J. Wilkins eds. 2000: 15-23.

MacDowell, D. 1971. Aristophanes’ Wasps. Edited with Introduction and Commentary. Oxford.

Momigliano, A. 1993 (1971). The Development of Greek Biography. Cambridge MA.

Olson, S. D. 2010. ‘Comedy, Politics, and Society.’ In G.W. Dobrov ed. 2010: 35-70.

Rashed, M. 2009. ‘Aristophanes and the Socrates of the Phaedo.’ OSAP 36: 107-36.

Rosen, R.M. 1988. Old Comedy and the Iambographic Tradition. Atlanta, GA.

    • 2000. ‘Cratinus’ Pytine and the Construction of the Comic Self.’ In D. Harvey and J. Wilkins eds. 2000: 23-40.
    • 2007. Making Mockery: the Poetics of Ancient Satire. Oxford.
    • 2010. ‘Aristophanes.’ In G.W. Dobrov ed. 2010: 227-78.

Rusten, J. ed. 2011. The Birth of Comedy. Texts, Documents, and Art from Athenian Comic Competitions, 486-280. Baltimore.

Scott, D. 2000. ‘Plato’s Critique of the Democratic Character.’ Phronesis 45: 19-37.

Sidwell, K. 1995. ‘Poetic Rivalry and the Caricature of Comic Poets: Cratinus’ Pytine and Aristophanes’ Wasps.’ In A. Griffith ed. 1995, Stage Directions: Essays in Ancient Drama in Honour of E. W. Handley. London. 56-80.

Sommerstein, A. H. ed. 1990-2012. The Comedies of Aristophanes. Warminster.

Storey, I. 2003. Eupolis: Poet of Old Comedy. Oxford.